Leading Christian Resource for Avid Readers, Support New Schools with Every Purchase.

Death Is That Man Taking Names: Intersections of American Medicine, Law, and Culture (Volume 7) (California/Milbank Books on Health and the Public)

Paperback |English |0520243242 | 9780520243248

Death Is That Man Taking Names: Intersections of American Medicine, Law, and Culture (Volume 7) (California/Milbank Books on Health and the Public)

Paperback |English |0520243242 | 9780520243248
Overview
Robert Burt has written a provocative and disturbing book that should be read by all professionals involved in end-of-life care. He suggests that dying patients, their families, and their physicians are "all vulnerable to unruly psychological forces unleashed by the imminent prospect of death" and that self-determination by patients is an inadequate safeguard against the many surrounding "forces of evil." He uses the legal and clinical examples of physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment to illustrate his thesis. Although I disagree with some of his conclusions and examples, the central themes deserve serious consideration. His first theme is that all persons facing end-of-life decisions are inherently ambivalent, with mixed emotions and motivations. Therefore, the notion of rational self-determination is an illusion in this context. However, the inherent limitations of rational decision making are relevant to all major medical decisions, not just those at the end of life. Because we are not purely rational beings, informed consent is always influenced by subjective and emotional factors. Yet it does not necessarily follow that informed consent and the self-determination of patients should be abandoned. Choice by individual patients, in and of itself, certainly does not preserve patients' autonomy any more than it encourages true informed consent. Clearly, the best end-of-life decisions are made as a result of the collaboration and mutual informing of the patient, the patient's family, and the physicians, each sharing his or her own expertise to help the patient make the best possible decision (often in the worst possible circumstances). Burt's second theme is the danger of secrecy, especially with regard to complex decisions that may give rise to ambivalence. This danger is particularly worrisome when the illusion of rationality is proposed as a safeguard. For example, decisions about do-not-resuscitate (DNR) orders used to be the exclusive province of physicians, until we learned that this secretive process was applied inconsistently and that physicians were unconsciously influenced by such factors as race, sex, and age. A more open, regulated practice was then developed, involving informed consent and creating additional challenges by putting more of this medical decision into the hands of patients. DNR decisions are still approached with ambivalence and are often influenced by irrational forces, but an open process ultimately offers better protection against nefarious forces than does overly simple reliance on patients' self-determination or physicians' beneficence. The third theme is that death has an "inherent aura of wrongdoing" and that it is "inherently evil." From this ominous perspective, considering death as a natural, inevitable part of the life cycle deprives it of its gravity and creates an illusion of moral neutrality. Death, it is argued, should not be accepted and certainly should not be chosen or consciously assisted. Extreme individual suffering should only be addressed by acts that involve "structured ambivalence" and not by acts that would explicitly and consciously hasten death. Burt further suggests that the psychological and spiritual toll taken on physicians by the regular confrontation of extremes of suffering and death explains some of the dark sides of medical practice, such as the seemingly irrational undertreatment of pain and the overuse of invasive medical technology in dying patients. He uses a selective reading of Freudian psychoanalysis to argue that physicians may punish patients in order to meet some unconscious psychic need to inflict added suffering. In support of this argument, he cites a study in which physicians maintained the use of paralytic drugs when they were withdrawing life support. Their motivation, in his view, was in part to protect the staff and family from witnessing the patient's struggle to breathe, but also, unconsciously, to punish the dying patient. I find the latter interpretation far-fetched. My belief is that the primary motivation for maintaining paralysis would be to help the dying patient, who is heavily sedated, to die more comfortably and quickly. Conversely, I would argue that one reason that paralytic drugs are sometimes discontinued in dying patients when life support is being withdrawn is so that ambiguity is injected back into the act, rather than because of any notion regarding protection of patients from suffering. In fact, dying patients are frequently undersedated when ventilators are being withdrawn, in order to create the kind of ambiguity that Burt is encouraging. Several examples from the broader field of end-of-life care also require the illusion of moral clarity in the face of ambiguity. For example, the rule of double effect requires that the sole intention of physicians be to relieve suffering, and that death, even when inevitable and desired by the patient, can only be foreseen and not intended by the physician. When a patient is ready to die and accepts the sedation that comes with increasing doses of pain medication, how can it be said that death is completely unintended? Similarly, when a patient is sedated to the point of unconsciousness to escape awareness of suffering and then is not provided with food or fluids, can it be realistically said that assistance in causing death is entirely unintended? Should not the patient and family be informed that death will be inevitable once the process has been started? The huge variation among hospice programs in the incidence of terminal sedation (ranging from 0 to 50 percent of deaths) should give us pause about the desirability of "structured ambivalence." One could argue that physician-assisted suicide is a much more ambiguous act than terminal sedation. After all, the physician's intent in prescribing the medication might be in part to help with sleep or to provide the reassurance that the patient could escape, but with the hope that he or she will choose not to do so. Thus, Burt's approach of creating "structured ambivalence" also carries the potential for self-deception and for manufactured ambiguity when clarity and honesty would better serve patients and families. In Death Is That Man Taking Names, Burt reminds us that irrational forces come into play in all end-of-life practices and that we deny them at peril to our patients and our profession. He persuasively argues that processes governing such practices should be open, that those involved should be accountable, and that standards should not be so unrealistic and idealized as to force the true complexity of these decisions to go unacknowledged. Although Burt applies his analysis mainly to physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment, it has broad applicability to other aspects of end-of-life care.Timothy E. Quill, M.D.Copyright © 2003 Massachusetts Medical Society. All rights reserved. The New England Journal of Medicine is a registered trademark of the MMS.--This text refers to an out of print or unavailable edition of this title.
ISBN: 0520243242
ISBN13: 9780520243248
Author: Robert A. Burt
Publisher: University of California Press
Format: Paperback
PublicationDate: 2004-09-06
Language: English
Edition: First
PageCount: 232
Dimensions: 6.0 x 0.63 x 9.0 inches
Weight: 12.8 ounces
Robert Burt has written a provocative and disturbing book that should be read by all professionals involved in end-of-life care. He suggests that dying patients, their families, and their physicians are "all vulnerable to unruly psychological forces unleashed by the imminent prospect of death" and that self-determination by patients is an inadequate safeguard against the many surrounding "forces of evil." He uses the legal and clinical examples of physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment to illustrate his thesis. Although I disagree with some of his conclusions and examples, the central themes deserve serious consideration. His first theme is that all persons facing end-of-life decisions are inherently ambivalent, with mixed emotions and motivations. Therefore, the notion of rational self-determination is an illusion in this context. However, the inherent limitations of rational decision making are relevant to all major medical decisions, not just those at the end of life. Because we are not purely rational beings, informed consent is always influenced by subjective and emotional factors. Yet it does not necessarily follow that informed consent and the self-determination of patients should be abandoned. Choice by individual patients, in and of itself, certainly does not preserve patients' autonomy any more than it encourages true informed consent. Clearly, the best end-of-life decisions are made as a result of the collaboration and mutual informing of the patient, the patient's family, and the physicians, each sharing his or her own expertise to help the patient make the best possible decision (often in the worst possible circumstances). Burt's second theme is the danger of secrecy, especially with regard to complex decisions that may give rise to ambivalence. This danger is particularly worrisome when the illusion of rationality is proposed as a safeguard. For example, decisions about do-not-resuscitate (DNR) orders used to be the exclusive province of physicians, until we learned that this secretive process was applied inconsistently and that physicians were unconsciously influenced by such factors as race, sex, and age. A more open, regulated practice was then developed, involving informed consent and creating additional challenges by putting more of this medical decision into the hands of patients. DNR decisions are still approached with ambivalence and are often influenced by irrational forces, but an open process ultimately offers better protection against nefarious forces than does overly simple reliance on patients' self-determination or physicians' beneficence. The third theme is that death has an "inherent aura of wrongdoing" and that it is "inherently evil." From this ominous perspective, considering death as a natural, inevitable part of the life cycle deprives it of its gravity and creates an illusion of moral neutrality. Death, it is argued, should not be accepted and certainly should not be chosen or consciously assisted. Extreme individual suffering should only be addressed by acts that involve "structured ambivalence" and not by acts that would explicitly and consciously hasten death. Burt further suggests that the psychological and spiritual toll taken on physicians by the regular confrontation of extremes of suffering and death explains some of the dark sides of medical practice, such as the seemingly irrational undertreatment of pain and the overuse of invasive medical technology in dying patients. He uses a selective reading of Freudian psychoanalysis to argue that physicians may punish patients in order to meet some unconscious psychic need to inflict added suffering. In support of this argument, he cites a study in which physicians maintained the use of paralytic drugs when they were withdrawing life support. Their motivation, in his view, was in part to protect the staff and family from witnessing the patient's struggle to breathe, but also, unconsciously, to punish the dying patient. I find the latter interpretation far-fetched. My belief is that the primary motivation for maintaining paralysis would be to help the dying patient, who is heavily sedated, to die more comfortably and quickly. Conversely, I would argue that one reason that paralytic drugs are sometimes discontinued in dying patients when life support is being withdrawn is so that ambiguity is injected back into the act, rather than because of any notion regarding protection of patients from suffering. In fact, dying patients are frequently undersedated when ventilators are being withdrawn, in order to create the kind of ambiguity that Burt is encouraging. Several examples from the broader field of end-of-life care also require the illusion of moral clarity in the face of ambiguity. For example, the rule of double effect requires that the sole intention of physicians be to relieve suffering, and that death, even when inevitable and desired by the patient, can only be foreseen and not intended by the physician. When a patient is ready to die and accepts the sedation that comes with increasing doses of pain medication, how can it be said that death is completely unintended? Similarly, when a patient is sedated to the point of unconsciousness to escape awareness of suffering and then is not provided with food or fluids, can it be realistically said that assistance in causing death is entirely unintended? Should not the patient and family be informed that death will be inevitable once the process has been started? The huge variation among hospice programs in the incidence of terminal sedation (ranging from 0 to 50 percent of deaths) should give us pause about the desirability of "structured ambivalence." One could argue that physician-assisted suicide is a much more ambiguous act than terminal sedation. After all, the physician's intent in prescribing the medication might be in part to help with sleep or to provide the reassurance that the patient could escape, but with the hope that he or she will choose not to do so. Thus, Burt's approach of creating "structured ambivalence" also carries the potential for self-deception and for manufactured ambiguity when clarity and honesty would better serve patients and families. In Death Is That Man Taking Names, Burt reminds us that irrational forces come into play in all end-of-life practices and that we deny them at peril to our patients and our profession. He persuasively argues that processes governing such practices should be open, that those involved should be accountable, and that standards should not be so unrealistic and idealized as to force the true complexity of these decisions to go unacknowledged. Although Burt applies his analysis mainly to physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment, it has broad applicability to other aspects of end-of-life care.Timothy E. Quill, M.D.Copyright © 2003 Massachusetts Medical Society. All rights reserved. The New England Journal of Medicine is a registered trademark of the MMS.--This text refers to an out of print or unavailable edition of this title.

Books - New and Used

The following guidelines apply to books:

  • New: A brand-new copy with cover and original protective wrapping intact. Books with markings of any kind on the cover or pages, books marked as "Bargain" or "Remainder," or with any other labels attached, may not be listed as New condition.
  • Used - Good: All pages and cover are intact (including the dust cover, if applicable). Spine may show signs of wear. Pages may include limited notes and highlighting. May include "From the library of" labels. Shrink wrap, dust covers, or boxed set case may be missing. Item may be missing bundled media.
  • Used - Acceptable: All pages and the cover are intact, but shrink wrap, dust covers, or boxed set case may be missing. Pages may include limited notes, highlighting, or minor water damage but the text is readable. Item may but the dust cover may be missing. Pages may include limited notes and highlighting, but the text cannot be obscured or unreadable.

Note: Some electronic material access codes are valid only for one user. For this reason, used books, including books listed in the Used – Like New condition, may not come with functional electronic material access codes.

Shipping Fees

  • Stevens Books offers FREE SHIPPING everywhere in the United States for ALL non-book orders, and $3.99 for each book.
  • Packages are shipped from Monday to Friday.
  • No additional fees and charges.

Delivery Times

The usual time for processing an order is 24 hours (1 business day), but may vary depending on the availability of products ordered. This period excludes delivery times, which depend on your geographic location.

Estimated delivery times:

  • Standard Shipping: 5-8 business days
  • Expedited Shipping: 3-5 business days

Shipping method varies depending on what is being shipped.  

Tracking
All orders are shipped with a tracking number. Once your order has left our warehouse, a confirmation e-mail with a tracking number will be sent to you. You will be able to track your package at all times. 

Damaged Parcel
If your package has been delivered in a PO Box, please note that we are not responsible for any damage that may result (consequences of extreme temperatures, theft, etc.). 

If you have any questions regarding shipping or want to know about the status of an order, please contact us or email to support@stevensbooks.com.

You may return most items within 30 days of delivery for a full refund.

To be eligible for a return, your item must be unused and in the same condition that you received it. It must also be in the original packaging.

Several types of goods are exempt from being returned. Perishable goods such as food, flowers, newspapers or magazines cannot be returned. We also do not accept products that are intimate or sanitary goods, hazardous materials, or flammable liquids or gases.

Additional non-returnable items:

  • Gift cards
  • Downloadable software products
  • Some health and personal care items

To complete your return, we require a tracking number, which shows the items which you already returned to us.
There are certain situations where only partial refunds are granted (if applicable)

  • Book with obvious signs of use
  • CD, DVD, VHS tape, software, video game, cassette tape, or vinyl record that has been opened
  • Any item not in its original condition, is damaged or missing parts for reasons not due to our error
  • Any item that is returned more than 30 days after delivery

Items returned to us as a result of our error will receive a full refund,some returns may be subject to a restocking fee of 7% of the total item price, please contact a customer care team member to see if your return is subject. Returns that arrived on time and were as described are subject to a restocking fee.

Items returned to us that were not the result of our error, including items returned to us due to an invalid or incomplete address, will be refunded the original item price less our standard restocking fees.

If the item is returned to us for any of the following reasons, a 15% restocking fee will be applied to your refund total and you will be asked to pay for return shipping:

  • Item(s) no longer needed or wanted.
  • Item(s) returned to us due to an invalid or incomplete address.
  • Item(s) returned to us that were not a result of our error.

You should expect to receive your refund within four weeks of giving your package to the return shipper, however, in many cases you will receive a refund more quickly. This time period includes the transit time for us to receive your return from the shipper (5 to 10 business days), the time it takes us to process your return once we receive it (3 to 5 business days), and the time it takes your bank to process our refund request (5 to 10 business days).

If you need to return an item, please Contact Us with your order number and details about the product you would like to return. We will respond quickly with instructions for how to return items from your order.


Shipping Cost


We'll pay the return shipping costs if the return is a result of our error (you received an incorrect or defective item, etc.). In other cases, you will be responsible for paying for your own shipping costs for returning your item. Shipping costs are non-refundable. If you receive a refund, the cost of return shipping will be deducted from your refund.

Depending on where you live, the time it may take for your exchanged product to reach you, may vary.

If you are shipping an item over $75, you should consider using a trackable shipping service or purchasing shipping insurance. We don’t guarantee that we will receive your returned item.

$13.78

    Condition

Arrives: -
In Stock

Overview
Robert Burt has written a provocative and disturbing book that should be read by all professionals involved in end-of-life care. He suggests that dying patients, their families, and their physicians are "all vulnerable to unruly psychological forces unleashed by the imminent prospect of death" and that self-determination by patients is an inadequate safeguard against the many surrounding "forces of evil." He uses the legal and clinical examples of physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment to illustrate his thesis. Although I disagree with some of his conclusions and examples, the central themes deserve serious consideration. His first theme is that all persons facing end-of-life decisions are inherently ambivalent, with mixed emotions and motivations. Therefore, the notion of rational self-determination is an illusion in this context. However, the inherent limitations of rational decision making are relevant to all major medical decisions, not just those at the end of life. Because we are not purely rational beings, informed consent is always influenced by subjective and emotional factors. Yet it does not necessarily follow that informed consent and the self-determination of patients should be abandoned. Choice by individual patients, in and of itself, certainly does not preserve patients' autonomy any more than it encourages true informed consent. Clearly, the best end-of-life decisions are made as a result of the collaboration and mutual informing of the patient, the patient's family, and the physicians, each sharing his or her own expertise to help the patient make the best possible decision (often in the worst possible circumstances). Burt's second theme is the danger of secrecy, especially with regard to complex decisions that may give rise to ambivalence. This danger is particularly worrisome when the illusion of rationality is proposed as a safeguard. For example, decisions about do-not-resuscitate (DNR) orders used to be the exclusive province of physicians, until we learned that this secretive process was applied inconsistently and that physicians were unconsciously influenced by such factors as race, sex, and age. A more open, regulated practice was then developed, involving informed consent and creating additional challenges by putting more of this medical decision into the hands of patients. DNR decisions are still approached with ambivalence and are often influenced by irrational forces, but an open process ultimately offers better protection against nefarious forces than does overly simple reliance on patients' self-determination or physicians' beneficence. The third theme is that death has an "inherent aura of wrongdoing" and that it is "inherently evil." From this ominous perspective, considering death as a natural, inevitable part of the life cycle deprives it of its gravity and creates an illusion of moral neutrality. Death, it is argued, should not be accepted and certainly should not be chosen or consciously assisted. Extreme individual suffering should only be addressed by acts that involve "structured ambivalence" and not by acts that would explicitly and consciously hasten death. Burt further suggests that the psychological and spiritual toll taken on physicians by the regular confrontation of extremes of suffering and death explains some of the dark sides of medical practice, such as the seemingly irrational undertreatment of pain and the overuse of invasive medical technology in dying patients. He uses a selective reading of Freudian psychoanalysis to argue that physicians may punish patients in order to meet some unconscious psychic need to inflict added suffering. In support of this argument, he cites a study in which physicians maintained the use of paralytic drugs when they were withdrawing life support. Their motivation, in his view, was in part to protect the staff and family from witnessing the patient's struggle to breathe, but also, unconsciously, to punish the dying patient. I find the latter interpretation far-fetched. My belief is that the primary motivation for maintaining paralysis would be to help the dying patient, who is heavily sedated, to die more comfortably and quickly. Conversely, I would argue that one reason that paralytic drugs are sometimes discontinued in dying patients when life support is being withdrawn is so that ambiguity is injected back into the act, rather than because of any notion regarding protection of patients from suffering. In fact, dying patients are frequently undersedated when ventilators are being withdrawn, in order to create the kind of ambiguity that Burt is encouraging. Several examples from the broader field of end-of-life care also require the illusion of moral clarity in the face of ambiguity. For example, the rule of double effect requires that the sole intention of physicians be to relieve suffering, and that death, even when inevitable and desired by the patient, can only be foreseen and not intended by the physician. When a patient is ready to die and accepts the sedation that comes with increasing doses of pain medication, how can it be said that death is completely unintended? Similarly, when a patient is sedated to the point of unconsciousness to escape awareness of suffering and then is not provided with food or fluids, can it be realistically said that assistance in causing death is entirely unintended? Should not the patient and family be informed that death will be inevitable once the process has been started? The huge variation among hospice programs in the incidence of terminal sedation (ranging from 0 to 50 percent of deaths) should give us pause about the desirability of "structured ambivalence." One could argue that physician-assisted suicide is a much more ambiguous act than terminal sedation. After all, the physician's intent in prescribing the medication might be in part to help with sleep or to provide the reassurance that the patient could escape, but with the hope that he or she will choose not to do so. Thus, Burt's approach of creating "structured ambivalence" also carries the potential for self-deception and for manufactured ambiguity when clarity and honesty would better serve patients and families. In Death Is That Man Taking Names, Burt reminds us that irrational forces come into play in all end-of-life practices and that we deny them at peril to our patients and our profession. He persuasively argues that processes governing such practices should be open, that those involved should be accountable, and that standards should not be so unrealistic and idealized as to force the true complexity of these decisions to go unacknowledged. Although Burt applies his analysis mainly to physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment, it has broad applicability to other aspects of end-of-life care.Timothy E. Quill, M.D.Copyright © 2003 Massachusetts Medical Society. All rights reserved. The New England Journal of Medicine is a registered trademark of the MMS.--This text refers to an out of print or unavailable edition of this title.
ISBN: 0520243242
ISBN13: 9780520243248
Author: Robert A. Burt
Publisher: University of California Press
Format: Paperback
PublicationDate: 2004-09-06
Language: English
Edition: First
PageCount: 232
Dimensions: 6.0 x 0.63 x 9.0 inches
Weight: 12.8 ounces
Robert Burt has written a provocative and disturbing book that should be read by all professionals involved in end-of-life care. He suggests that dying patients, their families, and their physicians are "all vulnerable to unruly psychological forces unleashed by the imminent prospect of death" and that self-determination by patients is an inadequate safeguard against the many surrounding "forces of evil." He uses the legal and clinical examples of physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment to illustrate his thesis. Although I disagree with some of his conclusions and examples, the central themes deserve serious consideration. His first theme is that all persons facing end-of-life decisions are inherently ambivalent, with mixed emotions and motivations. Therefore, the notion of rational self-determination is an illusion in this context. However, the inherent limitations of rational decision making are relevant to all major medical decisions, not just those at the end of life. Because we are not purely rational beings, informed consent is always influenced by subjective and emotional factors. Yet it does not necessarily follow that informed consent and the self-determination of patients should be abandoned. Choice by individual patients, in and of itself, certainly does not preserve patients' autonomy any more than it encourages true informed consent. Clearly, the best end-of-life decisions are made as a result of the collaboration and mutual informing of the patient, the patient's family, and the physicians, each sharing his or her own expertise to help the patient make the best possible decision (often in the worst possible circumstances). Burt's second theme is the danger of secrecy, especially with regard to complex decisions that may give rise to ambivalence. This danger is particularly worrisome when the illusion of rationality is proposed as a safeguard. For example, decisions about do-not-resuscitate (DNR) orders used to be the exclusive province of physicians, until we learned that this secretive process was applied inconsistently and that physicians were unconsciously influenced by such factors as race, sex, and age. A more open, regulated practice was then developed, involving informed consent and creating additional challenges by putting more of this medical decision into the hands of patients. DNR decisions are still approached with ambivalence and are often influenced by irrational forces, but an open process ultimately offers better protection against nefarious forces than does overly simple reliance on patients' self-determination or physicians' beneficence. The third theme is that death has an "inherent aura of wrongdoing" and that it is "inherently evil." From this ominous perspective, considering death as a natural, inevitable part of the life cycle deprives it of its gravity and creates an illusion of moral neutrality. Death, it is argued, should not be accepted and certainly should not be chosen or consciously assisted. Extreme individual suffering should only be addressed by acts that involve "structured ambivalence" and not by acts that would explicitly and consciously hasten death. Burt further suggests that the psychological and spiritual toll taken on physicians by the regular confrontation of extremes of suffering and death explains some of the dark sides of medical practice, such as the seemingly irrational undertreatment of pain and the overuse of invasive medical technology in dying patients. He uses a selective reading of Freudian psychoanalysis to argue that physicians may punish patients in order to meet some unconscious psychic need to inflict added suffering. In support of this argument, he cites a study in which physicians maintained the use of paralytic drugs when they were withdrawing life support. Their motivation, in his view, was in part to protect the staff and family from witnessing the patient's struggle to breathe, but also, unconsciously, to punish the dying patient. I find the latter interpretation far-fetched. My belief is that the primary motivation for maintaining paralysis would be to help the dying patient, who is heavily sedated, to die more comfortably and quickly. Conversely, I would argue that one reason that paralytic drugs are sometimes discontinued in dying patients when life support is being withdrawn is so that ambiguity is injected back into the act, rather than because of any notion regarding protection of patients from suffering. In fact, dying patients are frequently undersedated when ventilators are being withdrawn, in order to create the kind of ambiguity that Burt is encouraging. Several examples from the broader field of end-of-life care also require the illusion of moral clarity in the face of ambiguity. For example, the rule of double effect requires that the sole intention of physicians be to relieve suffering, and that death, even when inevitable and desired by the patient, can only be foreseen and not intended by the physician. When a patient is ready to die and accepts the sedation that comes with increasing doses of pain medication, how can it be said that death is completely unintended? Similarly, when a patient is sedated to the point of unconsciousness to escape awareness of suffering and then is not provided with food or fluids, can it be realistically said that assistance in causing death is entirely unintended? Should not the patient and family be informed that death will be inevitable once the process has been started? The huge variation among hospice programs in the incidence of terminal sedation (ranging from 0 to 50 percent of deaths) should give us pause about the desirability of "structured ambivalence." One could argue that physician-assisted suicide is a much more ambiguous act than terminal sedation. After all, the physician's intent in prescribing the medication might be in part to help with sleep or to provide the reassurance that the patient could escape, but with the hope that he or she will choose not to do so. Thus, Burt's approach of creating "structured ambivalence" also carries the potential for self-deception and for manufactured ambiguity when clarity and honesty would better serve patients and families. In Death Is That Man Taking Names, Burt reminds us that irrational forces come into play in all end-of-life practices and that we deny them at peril to our patients and our profession. He persuasively argues that processes governing such practices should be open, that those involved should be accountable, and that standards should not be so unrealistic and idealized as to force the true complexity of these decisions to go unacknowledged. Although Burt applies his analysis mainly to physician-assisted suicide, abortion, and capital punishment, it has broad applicability to other aspects of end-of-life care.Timothy E. Quill, M.D.Copyright © 2003 Massachusetts Medical Society. All rights reserved. The New England Journal of Medicine is a registered trademark of the MMS.--This text refers to an out of print or unavailable edition of this title.

Books - New and Used

The following guidelines apply to books:

  • New: A brand-new copy with cover and original protective wrapping intact. Books with markings of any kind on the cover or pages, books marked as "Bargain" or "Remainder," or with any other labels attached, may not be listed as New condition.
  • Used - Good: All pages and cover are intact (including the dust cover, if applicable). Spine may show signs of wear. Pages may include limited notes and highlighting. May include "From the library of" labels. Shrink wrap, dust covers, or boxed set case may be missing. Item may be missing bundled media.
  • Used - Acceptable: All pages and the cover are intact, but shrink wrap, dust covers, or boxed set case may be missing. Pages may include limited notes, highlighting, or minor water damage but the text is readable. Item may but the dust cover may be missing. Pages may include limited notes and highlighting, but the text cannot be obscured or unreadable.

Note: Some electronic material access codes are valid only for one user. For this reason, used books, including books listed in the Used – Like New condition, may not come with functional electronic material access codes.

Shipping Fees

  • Stevens Books offers FREE SHIPPING everywhere in the United States for ALL non-book orders, and $3.99 for each book.
  • Packages are shipped from Monday to Friday.
  • No additional fees and charges.

Delivery Times

The usual time for processing an order is 24 hours (1 business day), but may vary depending on the availability of products ordered. This period excludes delivery times, which depend on your geographic location.

Estimated delivery times:

  • Standard Shipping: 5-8 business days
  • Expedited Shipping: 3-5 business days

Shipping method varies depending on what is being shipped.  

Tracking
All orders are shipped with a tracking number. Once your order has left our warehouse, a confirmation e-mail with a tracking number will be sent to you. You will be able to track your package at all times. 

Damaged Parcel
If your package has been delivered in a PO Box, please note that we are not responsible for any damage that may result (consequences of extreme temperatures, theft, etc.). 

If you have any questions regarding shipping or want to know about the status of an order, please contact us or email to support@stevensbooks.com.

You may return most items within 30 days of delivery for a full refund.

To be eligible for a return, your item must be unused and in the same condition that you received it. It must also be in the original packaging.

Several types of goods are exempt from being returned. Perishable goods such as food, flowers, newspapers or magazines cannot be returned. We also do not accept products that are intimate or sanitary goods, hazardous materials, or flammable liquids or gases.

Additional non-returnable items:

  • Gift cards
  • Downloadable software products
  • Some health and personal care items

To complete your return, we require a tracking number, which shows the items which you already returned to us.
There are certain situations where only partial refunds are granted (if applicable)

  • Book with obvious signs of use
  • CD, DVD, VHS tape, software, video game, cassette tape, or vinyl record that has been opened
  • Any item not in its original condition, is damaged or missing parts for reasons not due to our error
  • Any item that is returned more than 30 days after delivery

Items returned to us as a result of our error will receive a full refund,some returns may be subject to a restocking fee of 7% of the total item price, please contact a customer care team member to see if your return is subject. Returns that arrived on time and were as described are subject to a restocking fee.

Items returned to us that were not the result of our error, including items returned to us due to an invalid or incomplete address, will be refunded the original item price less our standard restocking fees.

If the item is returned to us for any of the following reasons, a 15% restocking fee will be applied to your refund total and you will be asked to pay for return shipping:

  • Item(s) no longer needed or wanted.
  • Item(s) returned to us due to an invalid or incomplete address.
  • Item(s) returned to us that were not a result of our error.

You should expect to receive your refund within four weeks of giving your package to the return shipper, however, in many cases you will receive a refund more quickly. This time period includes the transit time for us to receive your return from the shipper (5 to 10 business days), the time it takes us to process your return once we receive it (3 to 5 business days), and the time it takes your bank to process our refund request (5 to 10 business days).

If you need to return an item, please Contact Us with your order number and details about the product you would like to return. We will respond quickly with instructions for how to return items from your order.


Shipping Cost


We'll pay the return shipping costs if the return is a result of our error (you received an incorrect or defective item, etc.). In other cases, you will be responsible for paying for your own shipping costs for returning your item. Shipping costs are non-refundable. If you receive a refund, the cost of return shipping will be deducted from your refund.

Depending on where you live, the time it may take for your exchanged product to reach you, may vary.

If you are shipping an item over $75, you should consider using a trackable shipping service or purchasing shipping insurance. We don’t guarantee that we will receive your returned item.

X

Oops!

Sorry, it looks like some products are not available in selected quantity.

OK

Sign up to the Stevens Books Newsletter

For the latest books, recommendations, author interviews and more

By signing up, I confirm that I'm over 16. To find out what personal data we collect and how we use it, please visit. our Privacy Policy.